This leads to the
conclusion. But according to the modern Naiyayikas, liege or the middle term
cannot be the operative cause of inference. It cannot lead to the conclusion
except through the knowledge of vyapti. Hence, they say that the knowledge of
vyapti should be taken as a special ground (karana), of inference. Vyapti does
directly lead to the conclusion. It has for its function the synthetic view of
the middle term as related to the major term, on the one hand, and of the minor
term, on the other. This is
liriga paramarsa. In this, the middle term is considered thrice. Hence, it is
maintained by the modern Naiyayikas that, while knowledge of the vyapti is a
special cause of inference, linga
paramarsa is the immediate cause of the conclusion. Some modern Naiyayikas, in
fact, say that linga paramarsa is the operative cause of the conclusion. Bradley’s analysis of inference
presents a similar picture. The premises, or the data, and the process of
inference consist in joining them into a whole by ideal construction. However,
as Chatterjee points out, liriga paramarsa is not an essential condition of all
inference although it may make an inference most cogent and convincing. In the
case of inference for oneself, we do not require more than the major and the minor
premise to arrive at the conclusion. There is a natural transition of thought
from the premises to the conclusion. In
the case of inference for others, we have to state the identity of the middle
term occurring in the two premises and exhibited in the third premise which
relates the same middle term to the minor and major terms.
Thus, it is generally agreed that inference is a mental
process, and the validity of inference is based on psychological and logical
grounds. The validity of inference depends on the knowledge of the universal
relation between the major and the middle term. It is also based on the
perception of the relation between the middle term and the minor. Perception of
the minor term as related to the middle term, and the recollection of the
universal relation between the major and the middle term, lead to the
conclusion of the relation between the minor term and the major. This is the
picture of the psychological ground of inference as presented by the Jainas and
other Indian philosophers. VIcDougall showed that all deductive reasoning
involves appreciative synthesis, although it is merely association. It is a
process of ‘mediate apperception’. In fact, he says, all types of reasoning are
processes of ‘mediate apperception’. They all make use of the ‘middle term’,
and this use oi the middle term is the sole and essential feature of reasoning,
in which it differs from other mental processes.
Structure of the Syllogism
All systems of Indian philosophy agree in holding that the
syllogism represents the typical form of expressing inference for others.
However, logicians are not agreed as to the number of propositions constituted
in a syllogism. Propositions are called avayavas. Some logicians say that there
are ten propositions in a syllogism. For instance, according to the old
Naiyayikas and also according to some Jaina logicians like Bhadrabhahu, a
syllogism consists of ten propositions. But Vatsyayana states that all the ten
members of syllogism are not logically necessary, although they may express the
psychological process of inference. Logicians generally agree that a syllogism
has five members. Gautama mentioned five members of the syllogism: (i) pratijnd the first statement, or an
assertion of what is to be proved, for instance, ‘the hill is fiery’, is pratijiza. It sets forth the thesis of
enquiry. The suggestion presented controls the process of inference from the
very start; (ii) hetu, states the
presence of the middle term. It gives the ground (sadhana), or the means of truth. For instance, it states dhurnat, ‘because of smoke’; (iii) udaharana states the universal
relation between the major and the middle term and gives examples in support of
its contention. It is a combination of the deductive and inductive processes.
It may be compared to Aristotle’s major premise with the establishment of the
universal proposition by means of examples. It presents an inductive process in
stating examples. Dr. Seal writes that the third member of the syllogism
combines and harmonizes Mill’s view of the major premise as a brief memorandum
of like instances already observed with the Aristotelian view of it as
universal proposition and a formal ground of induction; (iv) upanaya, the application of a universal proposition with its
examples to the subject for the minor term of the inference. It may be called
the minor premise of the syllogism. This may be affirmative or negative; (v) nigamana, the conclusion; it states,
“therefore the hill is on fire”. What is provisionally presented in the pratijna is finally accepted in the
conclusion. The Samkhya and Vaisesika systems accept the five
membered syllogism. But the Mimamsakas and the Vedantins do not accept the five
membered syllogism. According to them, a syllogism does not require more than
three members to carry conviction. The two essential conditions of valid
inference are the vyapti and the paksa dharmata, the presence of the
middle term and the minor term. Therefore, they contend, the three propositions
would be sufficient to give full force to the syllogistic inference. The three
propositions may be the first three like pratijna,
hetu and udaharana, or they may
be the last three, like uddharana,
upauaya and nigamana. The
Buddhists go further than the Mimarnsakas and reduce the syllogism to two
propositions only. This is analogous to the enthymeme in Western logic.
Among the Jaina logicians, Bhadrabahu seems to be in favour
of ten membered syllogisms, as we have mentioned earlier. In his Anasyaka Niryukti he describes the ten
propositions constituting a syllogism. They are constituted by the pratijiid, hetu and their vibhakti and vipaksa. Similarly, nka;iksa and akanksa pratisedha are the constituent propositions in such a
syllogism. Radhakrishnan says that Bhadrabahu here adopts the double method of
proof. When an argument is put forward, for instance, to prove the
nor.-eternity of sound, the counterproposition is asserted and denied by means
of the statement. How ever, Bhadrabahu says that the number of propositions in
a syllogism depends on the caliber of the person to whom it is addressed.
Accordingly, it may be a ten-membered syllogism or a five-membered syllogism.
Neither of these alternatives need be rejected. ‘We reject neither’. In the Pramanamimamsa, Hemacandra describes the
nature of the five propositions constituting a syllogism. Bhadrabahu’s
contention that the extent of the constituent propositions depends on the
ability of the persons to whom it is addressed, has great psychological
importance. It implies that the inference is limited by the capacity of the
individual’s understanding of the argument presented. Siddhasena Divakara
mentions five members in a syllogism. However, Das Gupta says that, regarding
inference, the Jainas hold that it is not necessary to have five propositions
in a syllogism. It is only the first two propositions that actually enter into
the inferential process. (vide Prarneya
kamalarrurrtanda, pp. 108-109.). When we make an inference, we do not
proceed through the five propositions. A syllogism consisting of five propositions
is rather for explaining a matter to a child than for representing the actual
state of the mind in making an inference.
Aristotle’s syllogism is a
purely formal and deductive form of inference. We have seen that, in Indian
thought, a distinction between deductive and inductive inference is not made.
An inference in Indian thought is both formally and materially true.
Aristotle’s syllogism begins with the major premise, and then it proceeds to
apply the universal proposition to a particular case. According to the Jainas
and also in all Indian thought, we first get the pratijna or the proposition to be proved. From the psychological
point of view, we do not, in fact, proceed in Aristotle’s way. We do not begin
with the universal proposition and then apply the universal proposition to a
particular case, unless it is to be a deliberate form of reasoning formally
presented. It would be psychologically correct to say that we first begin by
stating what is to be proved, and then find reasons to prove it. Aristotle’s
syllogism has more of a logical than a psychological status. W. E Johnson says
that it is commonly supposed that premises are propositions first presented in
thought, and that the transition from these to the thought of the conclusion is
the last step in the process. ‘But, in fact, the reverse is usually the case,
that is to say, we first entertain in thought the proposition that is
technically called the conclusion and then proceed to seek for other
propositions which would justify us in asserting it. A conclusion may, on the
one hand, first present itself to us as potentially assertable, in which case
the mental process of inference consists in transforming what was potentially
assertable into a proposition actually asserted’.
CHAPTER VII
SUPERNORMAL PERCEPTION
Introduction
The nature of empirical experience was discussed in the
last chapter. It was, by the earlier philosophers, called paroksa. Later philosophers, trying to adjust the original views
with the prevailing concepts of pratyaksa
and paroksa called it samvyavahara pratyaksa and made it arise
from the contact of the sense organs and the manas. But the empirical way of knowing may, at the most, give us
knowledge of the things of the world through the instrumentality of the sense
organs and mind. As such, according to the Jainas, it is not a direct
experience. It does not give us knowledge of reality. The Jainas believe that
the soul is pure and perfect, and omniscient. But through the obscuration of
the soul by the karma, the knowledge
that the soul has is obscured and vitiated. Once the veil of karma is removed, the soul knows
directly. That is pratyaksa. The
knowledge acquired through the sense organs and the manas is knowledge obtained indirectly by means of external
sources. The Jainas, therefore, said that such experience is paroksa, or what they later called samvyavahara pratyaksa We have, however,
the possibility of getting direct and immediate experience without the
instrumentality of the sense organs and the manas.
The soul directly cognizes as it is freed from the veil of karma. This is pratyaksa. It may be called supernormal perception. Modern
psychical research recognizes some such phenomenon and calls it extra-sensory
perception.
The problem of supernormal experience is not new. Indian
philosophers were aware of supernormal perception. Many of them made a
distinction between lacckika pratyaksa, empirical
perception, and alaukika pratyak.sa, supernormal
perception. All schools of Indian philosophy except the Carvakas and the
Mimamsakas believe in supernormal perception. The Carvakas do not accept any
other source of know ledge than sense perception. The Smarhsakas also deny the
possibility of supernormal perception, because, according to them, the past,
the future, the distant and the subtle can be known only by the injunctions of
the Vedas. Supernormal perception is not governed by the general laws of
perception. It transcends the categories of time, space and causality. The
facts of empirical experience cannot explain the nature of supernormal
perception. However, the Indian treatment of supernormal perception is more
descriptive than explanatory. It is not based on experimental analysis. The
Indian philosophers arrived at the conception of supernormal perception through
speculation and the higher intuition: Very often, the whole theory of the
gradation of supernormal perception is built on the basis of the transcendental
experience of the seers. The Nyaya Vaisesika, the Samkhya Yoga, the Vedanta,
the Buddhist and the Jaina schools of thought believe in supernormal
perception, although they have given different descriptions of the experience.
According to the Nyaya Vaisesika schools, perception is distinguished into laukika and
alaukika.
On the basis of the philosophy of the prakyti and the purusa, the
Sarhkhya philosophers maintain that supernormal perception can cognize past and
future objects, which are really existent as respectively sub-latent and
potential. Patanjali thinks that ordinary mental functions can be arrested by
constant practice of meditation and concentration. Samadhi is the
consummation of the long and arduous process of inhibition of the bodily
functions, concentration and meditation. The Vedantists accept Patanjali’s view
regarding supernormal perception.
In the West, modern scientists have begun to take more
interest in such perception, although they call it paranormal, and not
supernormal perception. It is also often called extra-sensory perception. The
Society ‘for Psychical Research has carried out investigations on this problem.
It is now recognized that cognition’s independent of the senses are possible.
Such phenomena as clairvoyance, telepathy and the like have been recorded to
prove the possibility of the occurrence of extra-sensory perception. But such
psychical research is entirely modern.’ It was founded in 1882. Myers and Henry
Sidgwick were the nucleus of research in this field. William Barest, the
physicist, was also a member of the Society. Many eminent philosophers and
psychologists took keen interest in the investigation of extra-sensory
perception. Prof. Bergen, C. D. Broad, L. P. Jacks, H. H. Price and R. H.
Thouless are among the supporters of this type of investigation. However,
interest in the study of extra-sensory perception may be said to be very old.
The first recorded psychical research in the West was carried out under
instructions from King Crocuses in the sixth century B.C. Wanting to test the
powers of the Oracles, he sent embassies with instructions to ask what the King
was doing at that time. But it was only in the 19th century that systematic
study of this problem was started with the establishment of the Society for
Psychical Research, The aim of the Society is to approach these various
problems without prejudice or prepossession of any kind and in the spirit of
exact and unimpassioned inquiry.
Going back to the Indian philosophers of the past, we find
that there has been a general recognition of the fact that normal perception
through sense organs and mind is not all. In the Nyaya Philosophy, specially beginning with Gatigesa, the distinction
between normal and supernormal perception has been recognized. However, in alaukika pratyaksa the objects are not actually present to the senses,
but are conveyed to it through an extraordinary medium. There is, in this, a
special sense object contact, alaukika
sannikarsa. There are three types of
supernormal perception , (i) Samantha
laksanu, in which we perceive the
generality in the individual members of a class, for instance, we perceive the
universal poutiness in the perception of individual pots. (ii) Janna laksana, in which we perceive an object which is in contact with the senses,
through previous knowledge of itself, for example, when we see a piece of
sandalwood there is also a perception of fragrance. This may be compared to
what Stout, Ward and Wundt call ‘complication’. But it would be difficult to call such forms of perception
supernormal.’ In fact, some psychologists would say it is a kind of implicit
inference, although Stout, Ward and Wundt would think of it as a form of
perception. However, such perception does not involve anything supernormal.
(iii) yogaja pratyaksa, intuitive apprehension of objects, past, future and
distant, through some supernormal powers generated in the mind by spiritual
concentration. For those who have
attained spiritual perfection such perception is constant and spontaneous. In
the case of others who are yet to reach perfection, it requires concentration
or dhyana, as a condition. Chatterjee says that we may
mention, as cases in point, the theological ideas of eternity and omniscience
or intuition in the philosophy of Spinoza and Schelling. Yogaja pratvaksa has a great bearing on the phenomena of extra-sensory perception like
Clairvoyance, Telepathy and Pre-cognition. However, yogaja pratyksa may be called
supernormal perception. Jayanta describes the nature of yogic perception. The
yogi can perceive a past, future, distant or subtle object. He can perceive
even Jayanta Bhatta says
that a yogi perceives all objects in a single intuition. Similarly,
Bhasaryaina defines yogic perception as direct and immediate apprehension of
objects which are distant or past, future or subtle.?, Prasastapada divides
yogic perception into two types, (i) yukta
pratyaksa, in which we get perception in
ecstasy, and (ii) viyukta
pratyaksa, which implies perception of
those who have fallen off from ecstasy. Bhasarvajna also makes a similar
distinction. Those who are in a state of ecstasy can perceive their own selves,
the selves of others, akasa, time, atoms and manas. Those who have fallen off
from ecstasy can perceive subtle, hidden or remote things through the contact
of the self, (manas), and senseorgans, with the object by means of a
peculiar power due to meditation. Similarly, Neo-Naiyayikas make a
two-fold distinction, between yukta
pratyaksa and vyanjana pratyaksa. In
the latter case, the individual getting the perception is still endeavoring to
attain union with the supreme being. Prasastapada mentions arsa jnana as a kind of yogic perception. It is an intuitive
apprehension of all objects, past, present and future, and also of dharma owing to the contact of manas with the self and a peculiar power, dharma,
born of austerities. It is sometimes said that arsalnaha and yogic perception
are different, because arsa-jnarra is produced
by the practice of austerities, while yogic perception is produced by
meditation. However, both are supersensuous in nature. But the Mimamsakas and
the Jainas do not accept the possibility of yogic’ perception because it cannot
be either sensuous or nonsensuous. It cannot be sensuous, as it is not produced
by contact of the sense organs and the rnanas.
Sense organs cannot come into contact with the past, the future and the
distant object. Nor can yogic perception be produced by the mind alone, as the
mind, without the help of the senseorgans, is capable of producing only mental
states like pleasure and pain. It is not also possible to maintain that the
external sense organs can apprehend objects, without coming into contact
through the powers of medicine, incantation and the practice of austerities,
because the senses are limited in their sphere. They cannot transcend their
natural limitations even when they attain the highest degree of perfection by
intense meditation. Therefore, the Mimarisaks say, yogic perception cannot be
sensuous, as sensuous knowledge cannot apprehend past, future and distant
objects. Similarly, if yogic perception can perceive what was apprehended in
the past, it would be mere recall or a form of memory. But if it cognizes more
than what was perceived in the past, it is illusory, as it apprehends something
which has no real existence. If yogic perception were perceptual in character,
it could not transgress the general conditions of perception, as it must be
produced by the contact of the sense organs with the object.
The Jainas also do not accept the possibility of yogic
perception as presented by the Nyaya Vaisesika Schools. The Jainas say that
sense organs are limited in their sphere and cannot be freed from their
inherent limitations. Even the sense organs of the yogis cannot apprehend
supersensible objects like atoms. The peculiar power of dharma born of meditation cannot be of any use to the sense organs
in directly apprehending supersensible objects. Dharma can neither increase the capacity of the sense-organs, nor
can it merely assist the sense organs in their function of apprehending
supersensible objects. Sense organs in themselves cannot apprehend
supersensible objects.
The Nyaya Vaisesika _ Schools _
maintain that the manas can get
simultaneous cognition of objects past, future and distant with the help of dharma born of yoga. But the Jainas say that the manas, which is regarded as atomic in nature, Cain never enter into
relation with all the objects of the world simultaneously. But it is contended
that, if the mind of a yogi can apprehend objects not simultaneously but
successively, yogic perception would not be different from ordinary perception.
Therefore, the Jainas say, yogic perception in the sense
presented by the Nyaya Vaisesika is not possible. Perception of all the objects
of the world can never be produced by the external sense organs or by the mind
even though aided by the peculiar power of dharma
born of meditation. The Jainas contend that it is the self which is responsible for such cognition. The self apprehends all the objects of the
world independently of the sense organs and the mind when the veil of karma is progressively removed.
The
Jaina View of Supernormal Perception
The Jaina account of supernormal
perception, is based on the Jaina metaphysics of the soul. In its pure state,
the soul is perfect, simple and unalloyed. It is pure
consciousness. But when it gets embodied, it moves in the wheel of samsara and experiences the things
of the world and its pleasures and
pains. The sense organs are the windows through which the soul gets empirical
experience. They are the instruments by which empirical experience is possible.
But when the veil of karma is removed,
the soul gets pure experience. The Jainas believe that the soul is inherently
capable of perceiving all things with all their characteristics. But this
capacity is obstructed by the karmas which
obscure real knowledge. Because of such obstruction by the knowledge-obscuring
and other kaznnas, it gets only an
imperfect knowledge of the objects of the world. The nature and extent of the
knowledge the soul gets will depend on the nature and extent of the obscuring
veil. But the knowledge of the soul is never totally obstructed by the veil,
even as the light of the sun or the moon
is never totally obstructed even by the darkest clouds. There is always some
glimpse of the external world however imperfect it may be. Complete destruction
of the veil of karma gives perfect
knowledge and omniscience.
On this basis, the Jainas divide pratyczksa into two kinds, (i) samvyavahara pratyaksa, empirical
perception which was originally called paroksa,
and (ii) pdramarthika pratyaksa, transcendental
perception. Empirical perception is what we get in every day experience. It is
of three
kinds; it may arise (i) from the sense organs, (ii) from the mind, which is a
quasi-sense organ, or (iii) from the sense organs and the mind. But as for
transcendental perception, the self gets this experience without the
help of the sense organs and the mind. It gets the experience directly when the
veil of the karma obscuring the knowledge is removed. This is a form of
supernormal perception. It was called pratyasa, because it is the direct experience
of the soul without the
instrumentality of the sense organs and the mind. It is of two kinds: (i)
imperfect, incomplete, or vikala, and (ii) perfect, complete, or
sakala. Vikala, is divided
into two types, (i) avadhi (clairvoyance) and (ii) manahparyaya
(telepathy). Perfect transcendental perception is omniscience. It is kevala. This is the stage of
supernormal perception. It is the perfect knowledge of all the objects
of the world through the complete destruction of the relevant obscuring karmas. It
is like the divine omniscience presented by the Nyaya Vaisesika schools-and--by
Patatijali. -But the Janis do not-believe in the existence of God. For them,
the soul itself is perfect and divine and
each individual soul an attain perfection and omniscience by completely
destroying the karmic matter which is an obstacle to the perfect knowledge.
When the veil of karma is destroyed, the soul realizes its omniscience.-,
According to the Jainas, the soul is inherently capable of cognizing all things
together with all their characteristics irrespective of spatial or temporal
distinctions. It is only because of the karmic veil that this capacity is
obscured. But it is possible that the veil of karma may not all be
destroyed although the relevant knowledge-obscuring karma may be removed.
Such annihilation of karma may be by degrees According to
the degree of annihilation of karma, the degree of supernormal
perception also varies. Omniscience occurs when there is complete. destruction
of the obscuring veil. But
when there are differences in the destruction of these veils the two varieties
of supernormal perception, avadhi and manalrparya,va, occur.
However, the Jainas believe that supernormal
perception in the form of avadhi, manahparyaya and kevala are
not dependent on the instrumentality of the sense organs and the manas. Only
normal perception needs the help of the sense organs and the manuals?
.The sense organs have no function in the case of supernormal
perception. It may also be said that, even in the case of empirical perception
like mati
and sruta, the role of the sense organs is subordinate, because the-sense organs serve to eliminate the
veil of karma
which obscures the knowledge of the _object. However, they have
their own function, because in the absence of these, empirical perception would
not be possible. Bhutabali, in his Mahabandha, sees the instrumental
role of the manas in the naanah paryaya jnana. But this view
need not be taken as representative. Akalanka_
_in-templates, in this case, manas as
Atman. In this sense, the Jnaina view
of supernormal perception is different from, the , crlaulcilca pratvaksa of the Naiyayikas. The forms of alaukika pratyksa are produced by
supernormal contact, alaukika-sannikarsa.
In this, there is a special type of contact
with the sense object. But the Jainas
do not accept such a special type of sense object contact. The sense organs are
limited in sphere. They do not have the capacity of coming into contact with
supersensible objects. The sense organs have no function in the case of
supernormal perception, as they cannot cognize the past, future and distant
objects. Therefore, empirical perception signifies direct and immediate
apprehension of gross objects produced by the contact of the organs with the objects determined in time and space and by
merit (punya) and demerit (pdpa). Supernormal perception is direct
and immediate cognition of all
objects past, future and distant. Recent psychical research shows that those
who are endowed with supernormal powers grasp the secret thoughts of other
individuals without using their sense organs. They also perceive events more or
less remote in space and time. In-supernormal perception,
Trans-spatial and Trans-temporal. relations are apprehended. There
is an ‘elsewhere’ in which the order of things would be different. We do not
come across the ‘elsewhere’ by means of empirical experience, because, in this,
we become aware of the external world by means of bodily sense organs which
have been specially developed to reveal it and nothing else. We may understand
this when we realize that our organs of sense perception are narrowly
specialized to serve biological and practical ends, and that our normal
consciousness is also largely specialized.
We have seen that the Jainas say that supernormal
perception is really pratyaksa, or
direct apprehension obtained by the soul when all the impediments are removed.
Supernormal perception has been classified as (i) avadhi, (ii) marrahparyayci, and (iii) kevala. The distinction between vikala
and sakala pratyaksa has also
been mentioned. The three forms of supernormal perception mentioned by the
Jainas may appear, Tight appoints out. . to-be- dogmatic.
However, it may be noted that the vital source of the Jaina theory of knowledge
lies in this conception. If the soul has the capacity to know, it must know
independently of any external conditions. Distance, spatial or temporal, is not
a hindrance to the soul.?
C. D. Broad says that forms of supernormal cognition may be
classified as follows: We may divide them into (i) supernormal cognitions of
contemporary events or of contemporary states of mind, and (ii) super normal
cognitions of past or future events or past or future things or persons. Under
the first heading, we can include clairvoyance and telepathy. In the second
type, we may include supernormal cognition of past events, for instance,
knowledge of the past as claimed by Miss Moberley in her book An
Adventure, and supernormal precognition, knowledge of the future, as
is claimed by Dunne in his book, An Experiment with Time. The analysis
here will be restricted to the study of clairvoyance and telepathy with
reference to avadhi and mauahparyaya. Then a brief survey of
omniscience, or kevala jiana, as the Jainas have presented it, will be given.
Other forms of extra-sensory perception like mediumship, automatic writing and
poltergeists have been of interest to modern psychical research. Flew analyses
the forms of extra-sensory perception into spontaneous phenomena, psychical and
mental, and mediumship, physical and mental. However, these forms of
extra-sensory perception do not come within the purview of this discussion.
Avadhi
Avadhi jnana is a form of supernormal
perception. It is pratyaksa, or direct perception, because the soul gets direct
apprehension of the object without the
help. of the sense organs and the mind. In this, we apprehend
objects which are beyond the reach of the sense organs and the mind. In this,
we apprechend objects which are beyond the reach of the sense organs. However,
in avadhi
we perceive only such things as have form and shape This can be
compared with clairvoyance, which modern psychical research calls a form of
extra-sensory perception. Things without form, like the soul and dharma, cannot
be perceived by avadhi. Clairvoyance of this type differs with different
individuals according to their capacity, developed by them through their merit.
Owing to the varying degree of destruction and subsidence of the karmic veil,
the individual can perceive supersensible objects in different degrees. The
highest type of avadhi can perceive all objects having form. The Jainas
interpret the capacity of perception in avadhi jnana in terms of -space
and time. They have developed a technique of mathematical calculation of the
subtleties of time and space. Regarding space, cmadhi jnana can extend
over a space occupied by innumerable pradesas of the size of the universe.
With reference to time, it can perceive through innumerable points of time both
past and future. Avadhi can perceive all modes of all things. But it cognizes
only a part of the modes of things according to the degree of intensity of
perception. The lowest type of avadhi can perceive an object occupying
a very small fraction of space, e. g., the angula. Regarding capacity in terms of
time, the lowest type of avadhi can last only a short time, a
second. It cannot extend beyond a second. Similarly, it cannot know all the
modes of objects.’ It can only cognize a part of the modes. Thus, avadhi, which may be
compared to clairvoyance, differs with different individuals according to the
capacity of the persons perceiving. The capacity is, in turn, determined by the
relative merit acquired by the persons.
Modern psychical research has provided many examples of
such persons. Experimental investigation has been carried out in this field.
For instance, Prof. Rhine and his colleagues at Duke University carried out
experiments with a pack of zener cards and arrived at astonishing results.
Perception beyond an opaque wall, precognition and fore-knowledge have been of
great interest to para-psychology. Even Kant was greatly interested in
ostensible clairvoyance, by Swedenborg, with reference to Queen Lovisa in 1761
and his clairvoyant cognition of the Stockholm fire. Dreams which foretell events
may also be included-in such forms of perception. The Society for Psychical
Research has collected many such instances. For instance, the Hon. J. O. _
Connor, about ten days before the Titanic sailed, saw in a dream that the
ship floating in the sea, keel upwards, and her passengers and crew swimming
around. In another case, a lady dreamt that her uncle had fallen from horseback
and died. She also dreamt he was brought home in a wagon. ‘There in my dream
the wagon came to the door. And two men, well-known to me, helped to carry ‘the
body upstairs. I saw the man carrying the body with difficulty, and his left
hand hanging down and striking against the bannisters, as the men mounted the
stairs’. Later, the dream recurred thrice, with all the details unchanged. This
was followed by her uncle’s death in exactly the same situation as she had
dreamt, and he was carried home in the same way with his left hand hanging and
striking against the bannisters as the men mounted the stairs. In
our country, we get many instances of dreams and such forms of perception is
necessary.
To turn to ancient., Indian - thought,
Prasastapada and Jayant Bhatta say that, though yogis can perceive all objects
past, future and distant, even ~ ordinary persons like us are not entirely
devoid of such perception. Some men have the power of perceiving the future. On
rare occasions, we get a flash of intuition, as for instance, when a girl
perceives in her heart of hearts that her brother will come to-morrow.- These
may be included under the form of avadhi perception. However, they cannot
be called supernormal perception. They are extra-sensory or para-normal
perception, yet not abnormal mental phenomena. The Jainas also do not make avadhi a form of
supernormal perception in this sense, because, according to them, beings living
in hell, and even the lower organisms, are capable of possessing avadhi, although, in general it may be included in the supernormal perception.
Modern psychical research is also aware of the possibility of such a form of
perception in the higher vertebrates. In
the commentary on verse V of Dravvasgdigraha,
Ghoshal says that avadhi jnana is psychic knowledge which is directly acquired by the soul without the
instrumentality of the mind and the senses. He cites knowledge in a hypnotic
state as an instance of avadhi. But it would not be correct to compare avadhi to
knowledge in a hypnotic state, although the description of avadhi as
direct cognition without the help of the sense organs and the mind would be
correct. The hypnotic state is a state of hyper-suggestion and an abnormal
mental state. In this sense, avadhi
cannot be called a state of
hyper-suggestion and it would not be proper to reduce avadhi to
an abnormal mental state.
The Jainas have given a detailed analysis
of avadhi and of
beings who possess avadhi. According
to the Jainas, heavenly beings and beings in hell possess avadhi naturally. They are endowed with it from birth. It
is bhava pratyaya in
them, possibly because they do not possess bodily sense organs like human
beings. In the case of human beings as well as five-sensed lower organisms, avadhi is possible owing to the destruction and subsidence
of the relevant veil of karma. It is
acquired by merit. Therefore, it is called enapraty
aTa.2. Thus, human beings and the lower organisms have to
acquire avadhi by
effort, while the beings residing in heaven and hell get it naturally. Visesavasyakabhasya gives a detailed description of
avadhi from
fourteen points of view and its varieties with
reference to temporal and spatial extension.? Panc astiknyasara, divides avadhi into three types with reference to spatial
extension, desavadhi, paramavadhi and sarvavadhi. All three are conditioned by psychic qualities,
but desavadhi is also
conditioned by birth in the case of heavenly beings and beings in hell. Desavadhi is a very limited faculty of perceiving things
beyond sense perception. Paramavadhi is a higher
form of perception which is not confined to a limited space and time. But sarvavadhi is the perfect faculty which perceives all things.
Desavadhi_ is divided
into two types, gunapratyaya and bhavapratyaya, with their subdivisions. Nandisutra gives six varieties- of avadhi, which
are possible in the ease of homeless ascetics. It also mentions subdivisions
[Please
see the Table in file name “Page No. 135
is Table”]
of these. A table of
classification of avadhi according to the Nandisutra is given Tin table
No. VIII. The first variety, for instance, is arrugarni avadhi. It is
clairvoyance, which continues to exist even if a person moves elsewhere. Ananugami avadhi is the opposite of
this. Vardhamaua
avadhi is that which increases in extensity and extends in scope and
durability as time passes. Hiyamana is opposed to this. Avasthita
is a steady form of avadhi which neither increases nor
decreases in scope or durability. The sixth form of avadhi is anavasthitha. It sometimes
increases and sometimes decreases in intensity. Such classifications of avadhi with
their subdivisions have a psychological significance. It is possible that
clairvoyant cognition may differ in different individuals in respect of
intensity and durability of experience and the extent of the objects perceived
by the individual. There are instances in which some persons get occasional
flashes of perception, as in the case of a girl who got the intuition that her
brother would come. In some other cases, clairvoyance is more or less steady,
and it recurs very often. The Society for Psychical Research has collected many
instances of such perceptions. The scope of clairvoyant cognition with
reference to the objects cognized varies with the sensitiveness and extent of
contact of the subliminal consciousness. Different persons can perceive
different objects with different degrees of clarity according to their
capacities. The Jainas have said that the lowest type of avadhi can perceive
objects occupying a very small fraction of space like the angula. The highest, type
of avadhi
can perceive all objects having form. However, avadhi cannot perceive all
the modes of all things.
The psychic phenomenon called ‘French sensitiveness’,
sometimes called as ‘psychometry’, may be
included as a form of although in
psychometry the mind and the sense organs do play their part. There may be
physical contact with the object. However, physical contact serves only as an
occasion to create a ‘a psychical rapport’. The role of the object coming in
contact with the hand of the person would seem to be rather to canalize the
sensitive faculty and concentrate it in the right direction, though we have no
information as to how it happens. Dr. Osley gives
many instances in which persons having this capacity have given detailed
descriptions of the past or the future by merely touching the hand or even by
touching a paper written by the person. He gives an experience which he had. An
event in his ‘life, an accident, was foretold twice. The man who described the
future accident gave a vivid picture of the accident, of the man, a baker,
bleeding and things strewn about. The accident occurred exactly as it was
predicted. Tyrrell cites many such instances. Dr. Osley says that, if we are to
take the language of the permanently metagnomic subjects literally, one might
think...... that they perceive realities as if by a paranormal optical sense outside
time and space. They grasp from an ultra-material plane and see things as they
would occur. - There seems to be one major difference between the description
of perception given .by Dr. Osley and the nature of avadhi. We have seen that
avadhi
does not make use of the sense organs and the mind. But Osley
describes the phenomenon as perception of realities ‘as if by a paranormal
optical sense outside space and time.’ This is not very clear. However, the
optical sense outside time and space need not refer to the functions of the
physical sense organs. Moreover, Dr. Osley says that the perception is as if by
a paranormal optical sense. C. D. Broad admits that clairvoyance is
non-sensuous perception. He interprets an experiment with red cards in the
following terms: “We shall have to suppose that the clairvoyant has, from
infancy, been continuously though unconsciously apprehending directly all those
objects which he has also been cognizing indirectly through sight and touch.
Then we can suppose that an association would be set up between, e.g. the
conscious experience of seeing an object as red and the unconscious experience
of directly apprehending it as having that intrinsic characteristic which makes
it selectively reflect red-stimulating light-waves. Suppose that, on some
future occasion, such an object, though no longer visible, is still being
directly but unconsciously apprehended by the clairvoyant. He will still
apprehend it as having that intrinsic characteristic, whatever it may be, which
has now become associated in his mind with the visual appearance of redness.
Consequently, the idea of it as a red-looking object will arise automatically
in his mind, and he will announce that the unseen object is red”. Whatever may
be the explanation of clairvoyant cognition, it cannot be denied that such
experiences are facts. Eminent philosophers like Sidgwick, Price and Broad have
admitted the existence of such clairvoyant experiences.
Mana hparyaya
Now we come to the next form of supernormal perception,
called by the Jainas manahparyaya. The Jaina concept of manahparyaya
is based on their doctrine of mind. We have seen that mind,
according to Jainas, is a particular material substance composed of a specific form of varganus, or group of atoms, It is
composed of an infinite number-of atoms called manovarganas. There are
fine atoms. The finer atoms form the karma. Next in fineness come the manovarganns.
They occupy less space. The other groups of atoms form the subtle
and the gross body. The modes of the mind are different states emerging into
acts of thought. Every state of our mind is a particular mode of mind. As our
states of thought change, the mind also changes. Every mode of thought is
reflected in the mind substance. Direct experience of such modes of mind substance
working in other individual minds is called manahparyaya. Avasyakaniryukti gives a
brief description of the nature of manahparyaya knowledge. Manhparyaya
cognizes objects thought of by the minds of other people. In the Visesavasyakabhasya,
we get a description of the manahparyaya jnana. A person possessing
manahparyaya
directly cognizes the mental states of others without the
instrumentality of the sense organs and the mind.s We have seen that Bhutabali
admits the instrumentality of manas in this experience, but his view
is not generally accepted.
In Western thought, such a form of cognition was called ‘thought
transference.’ But, as Tyrrell says, since the name gives a wrong suggestion
that something was being transferred through the space, it is not adequate.
Myers coined the phrase ‘telepathy’ for describing such experiences. Tyrrell
gives many instances of telepathic cognition. He also mentions instances of
collective telepathy which he calls collective telepathic calculations. In Apparitions,
published by the Society for Psychical Research, many interesting
examples of telepathic cognition are recorded. It is not possible to go through
the many instances of telepathy which Western scientists have recognized.
Coming back to the Jaina view, we find that manahparyaya,
telepathic experience, is not easy to get and is not common. A
certain physical and mental discipline is a condition for getting their power
of intuition. In the Avasykaniryukti we read that manahparyaya
is possible only for human beings of character, especially for
homeless ascetics. Human beings acquire this capacity through merit and by the
practice of mental and moral discipline, In the Nandisutra there is a
detailed description of the conditions of the possibility of manahparyaya
in the case of human beings. Manahparyaya is possible only in this karmabhumi,
this world of activity, this empirical world. Even the gods are not
competent to possess manahparyaya. Only
gifted human beings with a definite span of life can acquire this faculty. Some
conditions have to be fulfilled and some discipline has to be undergone by
human beings for acquiring manahparyaya. The conditions for the
possession of manahparyaya are: (i) the human beings in the karmabhumi must have fully developed sense organs and a fully developed personality.
They must be paryapta; (ii) they must possess the right attitude, (samyagdrsti). As a consequence, they must be free from passion; (iii) they must be
self-controlled and they must be possessed of rddhi, extraordinary powers.
Thus, telepathic cognition is not
possible for all beings. Only human beings can acquire it. It is conditioned by
a strict physical and mental discipline. The person possessing it must
necessarily be a hermit, or homeless ascetic. His character must be of a high
type. The discipline and the occult powers attainable by the yogis mentioned in
the Patanjali Yoga are analogous to the qualifications of human beings
possessing manahparyuva. But
Siddhasena Divakara says that lower organisms possessing two or more sense
organs are also found to strive by means of attraction or repulsion; therefore,
they are possessed of mind. It would, hence, be proper to extend the scope of manahparyaya to such lower organisms. It
would be improper to postulate manahparyaya as a
separate category of knowledge. In this connection, we may refer to modern
psychical research in telepathy described by Rhine says that it is possible to
find instances of the possibility of such perceptions in the case of lower
animals, especially the higher vertebrates. Several experiments have been
carried out in this connection and several instances have been quoted. But the
traditional Jaina view does not accept the possibility of manahparyaya in the case of the lower
animals. It restricts the scope of such cognition to human beings.
Objects
of Cognition in Manahparyaya
Although there is among the Jainas,
general agreement on the nature of manahparyaya, the
Jaina philosophers are not agreed regarding the objects of the cognition
possible in this experience. Various views have been presented. Jinabhadra
states that one who possesses manahparyaya perceives
the states of mind of others directly. But external objects thought of by the
minds of others are only indirectly cognized through inference. Hemacandra,
commenting on the statement of Jinabhadra, says that a man may think of a
material object as well as of a non-material object. But it is impossible to
perceive a non-material object directly except by one who is omniscient.
Therefore, one who is possessed of manahparyaya, telepathic
cognition, knows external objects thought of by others only indirectly, by
means of inference. The function of telepathy is restricted to perceiving
mental states, like thoughts and ideas, of others. External objects are the
content of these mental states. They are not possible to be cognized directly in manahparyayti.
They are known indirectly by inference, as they are associated
through the media of states of the mind, although such knowledge is not of the
type of ordinary inference. Hemacandra also supports this view of restricting
telepathy to cognition of mental states of others. He says that cognition of
external objects thought of by others is indirect, as it is by necessary
implication from the perception of thoughts which are not possible without
objects. On the other hand, Unlasvati says that manahparyaya cognizes
states of mind and material objects thought of by the minds of others. The mind
undergoes a process of change while thinking, and the object content of this
process is intuited by marrahparyaya. One who is possessed of manahparyaya
knows only a fractional part of the objects of clairvoyance. He
knows a greater number of the states of the material objects that form the
content of the invisible process of the mind. Thus, according to Umasvati, the
scope of telepathy is larger, because it includes cognition of external objects
thought of by others in addition to mental states. But Siddhasena Divakara
seems to interpret this statement of Umasvati in the light of the view
presented by Jinabhadra. He says that objects are cognized indirectly through
inference. However, this does not seem to be the proper interpretation of
Umasvati, because we have seen that objects forming the content of the mind are
directly cognized. The statement of Umasvati lends itself to this
interpretation. We now come to a third view regarding the object of manahparyaya.
This view is presented by Pujypada Devanandi. He says that external objects are also intuited by manahparyaya.
Manahparyaya is a form of pratyaksa in the traditional sense of
the term. It is independent of the instrumentality of the sense organs and the
mind. It does not involve inference, which depends on the sense organs such as
eyes and also on the information of others.s According to his view, manahparyaya
has wider scope, as it cognizes external objects directly. We may
say it includes avadhi, or clairvoyance, also. There is agreement as to the nature of manahparyaya as pratyaksa,
but regarding intuition of external objects there has been a
difference of opinion. We have seen that Jinabhadra does not accept the
possibility of direct cognition of external objects in manahparyaya. He
introduces inference for explaining this kind of cognition. Pujyapada Devanandi
has widened the scope of manahparyaya by including direct
perception of external objects also. Akalanka says that states of the mind are
only the media through which external objects are intuited. Umasvati accepted
the direct perception of external objects thought of by others in manahparyaya.
The question of the scope of
manahparyaya is not psychologically significant.
Those who accept telepathy as a form of supernormal’ experience do not make
such a distinction. Telepathy is primarily concerned with cognition of the
thoughts of others. It was, therefore, called ‘thought transference’. In this,
the mental states of others are intuited. But the objects forming the content
of the mental states are not excluded from the scope of telepathic cognition,
although it is not explicitly mentioned. However, it would also be possible to
maintain that cognition of objects forming the content of the mental states may
be included in the field of clairvoyant experience, because clairvoyance
cognizes objects which are beyond spatial and temporal relations.
Classification
of Manahparyaya
Sthananga
recognizes two varieties of manahparyaya as rjumati and vipulamati. Umasvati
makes a similar distinction. He says that rjumati is less pure and it sometimes
falters. Vipulamati is purer and more lasting. It lasts up to the rise of
omniscience. We also get such an account in Paneastikayasara. Rjumati gives a
direct intuition of the thoughts of others, while in vipulamati the process of
knowing the ideas of others is manifested in an irregular way. Pujyapada
Devanandi describes the nature of manahparyaya as intuition of the objects of
the activities of the sense organs. He says that vipulamati knows less objects
than rjumati, but whatever it knows it knows perfectly and vividly; vipulamati
is more penetrating and more lucid than rjurnati.